************************************************************************
REEDINGS
. . .
************************************************************************
GIFFORD LECTURE CONTRASTS:
HAUERWAS & McINERNY
Before turning to this task, Hauerwas tries to explain why someone like
himself (who like Karl Barth basically denies the possibility of "natural
theology") would accept the invitation to give the Gifford Lectures.
In self-defense, he notes that another Gifford lecturer, Alasdair
MacIntyre, refused to do the "scientific" work mandated by Lord Gifford’s
will, which amply endowed the project. Rather,
following the lead of St. Thomas Aquinas, MacIntyre set forth a "natural
theology" rooted in the analogy of being, following principles quite different
from the "natural theology" shaped by the Enlightenment.
The Enlightenment, as Hauerwas has incessantly argued, birthed the
"modernity" that has subverted the Christian faith and community.
Citing a recent work by Matthew Bagger, Hauerwas says that "’the rise
of human self-assertion following the breakdown of the medieval world-view
captures the central features of modern thought and culture.
Modernity represents the outcomes of a dialectic motivated by
contradictions within medieval theology. Self-assertion
requires that humans give themselves the standards of thought and action rather
than seeking them from an external source, like God’" (p. 32, quoting Religious
Experience, Justification, and History, p. 212).
Consequently, Immanuel "Kant became the exemplary Protestant
theologian, and Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone became the
great text in Protestant moral theology" (p. 38).
Rooted in Kant, F.D.E. Schleiermacher, Albert Ritschl, and Ernst
Troeltsch shaped the "Protestant Liberalism" that has significantly shaped
the theology Hauerwas rejects.
Though hardly a theologian, William James illustrates the religious
sentiments of liberalism--and the religious pragmatism that so distresses
Hauerwas. Under
Such pragmatism, Hauerwas rightly avers, has deeply dyed 20th century
Christianity. Discarding doctrine,
under the impression that science has disproved its traditional assertions,
modernists easily appropriated James’s approach:
believe whatever helps you cope with life, affirm whatever enables you to
succeed, embrace whatever makes you feel good.
Such a "natural theology," focused upon "natural man," proposed
an optimistic humanism fleshed out for popular consumption by preachers such as
Norman Vincent Peale and Robert Schuller. Reducing
theology to psychology, joining arms with secularists in shaping today’s
therapeutic culture, the followers of William James are legion.
So to carefully critique James is most helpful.
Unlike James, Reinhold Niebuhr defines himself as a Christian theologian,
though his real concern was social ethics. Sometimes
lumped with "Neo-Orthodox" thinkers, in that he rejected some of the
liberalism of his early years, Niebuhr was, Hauerwas insists, fully committed to
the liberal agenda. Indeed, Hauerwas
argues, "Neibuhr’s Gifford Lectures [The Nature and Destiny of Man]
are but a Christianized version of James’s account of religious experience"
(p. 87). Politically, this was
markedly evident in Niebuhr’s support for Norman Thomas (perennially the
Socialist Party candidate for President) and alignment with the notoriously
left-wing Americans for Democratic Action. Consequently,
Hauerwas caustically observes, "Niebuhr’s theology seems to be a perfect
exemplification of Ludwig Feuerbach’s argument that theology, in spite of its
pretentious presumption that its subject matter is God, is in fact but a
disguised way to talk about humanity" (p. 115).
That Hauerwas may not be overly severe in his criticism finds support in
a 1947 letter John Dewey wrote. An
atheist, fully committed to his own version of pragmatism, Dewey was a
reasonably dispassionate critic. He
noted that both Niebuhr and Kierkegaard "’have completely lost faith in
traditional statements of Christianity, haven’t got any modern substitute and
so are making up, off the bat, something which supplies to them the gist of
Christianity--what they find significant in it and what they approve of in
modern thought--as when two newspapers are joined.
The new organ says "retaining the best features of both"’" (p.
97).
So Niebuhr, Hauerwas says, shares James’s pragmatic approach and fails
to uphold authentic Christianity. His
critique of liberalism fails because he never really abandoned liberalism.
Having myself recently read The Nature and Destiny of Man,
however, I suspect Hauerwas protests too much!
While Niebuhr’s "theology" may be faulted for various failures, he
is primarily a social ethicist and apparently had little aptitude for or
interest in the classical issues of theology.
I suspect Hauerwas dislikes Niebuhr’s politics, particularly his
approval of
Repudiating the approach of James and Niebuhr, both of whom certainly set
forth a form of "natural theology," Hauerwas appropriates, as an ally, Karl
Barth, well known for his staunch "Nein!" to Emile Brunner’s
defense of natural theology. In
Barth Hauerwas finds the man, and the theology, worth celebrating.
Amazingly, Hauerwas endeavors to show that Barth rightly set forth a
"natural theology." He says this
despite Barth’s vehement opposition to such!
He claims Barth "provides the resources necessary for developing an
adequate theological metaphysics, or, in other words, a natural theology.
Of course, I assume that ‘natural theology’ simply names how
Christian convictions work to describe all that is as God’s good creation"
(p. 142). However problematic, this
"assumption" allows Hauerwas to build his case!
This leads Hauerwas to an intricately detailed discussion, rooted in an
appreciative reading of Barth’s Church
Dogmatics, designed to show why--and in what ways--he is remarkably akin to
Thomas Aquinas! This is because both
men, Hauerwas insists, relied upon the analogia fidei, the analogy of
faith. We can think about God
only in terms of "like" and "as," taking clues from visible realities
discern invisible Reality. Moving
from the created world, the natural world, to the Creator, involves thinking
analogically. Barth’s
understanding of God, derived from Revelation, works itself out, Hauerwas says,
in metaphysical categories and ethical imperatives.
Both Barth himself and his Dogmatics were "witnesses" to this
endeavor, Hauerwas says. This leads
him, in the book’s eighth and final chapter, to set forth his own position,
"The Necessity of Witness." Here
familiar Hauerwas themes appear. Whereas
Barth was mainly concerned that we "let God be God," Hauerwas’s message is
"let the church must be the church," living out the radical imperatives of
the Gospel. In an authentic
community of faith, worship and praise incubate and shape theological
reflection. He cites John Howard
Yoder and Pope John Paul II as demonstrations as to how this is done in our
day--especially insofar as they espouse non-violence (Hauerwas’s special
passion).
This book’s value, in my judgment, lies in its probing, richly
footnoted discussion of James, Niebuhr and Barth.
Though Hauerwas’s interpretations can never be taken at face value,
they prod one to think and see new dimensions to these thinkers.
When he sets forth his own views, however, things turn more problematic.
Take, for instance, his contention that "witness" is crucial for the
church. There must be no disparity
between one’s beliefs and acts. Thus
he sternly rebukes allegedly "Christian universities" for failing to be
Christian. Indeed, he declares,
"we should not be surprised that the most significant intellectual work in our
time may well take place outside the university" (p. 232).
Yet, one must remember, Professor Hauerwas himself teaches at
Still more, it seems to me that as one considers Hauerwas’s allegedly
"radical" positions, it becomes clear that he almost unfailingly appeases
the modern academic intelligentsia, of which he is a celebrated insider.
To criticize liberalism, in today’s post-modern academic environs,
costs one very little. To share
Stanley Fish’s constructivist, reader response approach to hermeneutics,
places one comfortably at the center of today’s triumphant secularism.
To trumpet one’s Anti-Americanism, as Hauerwas routinely does, enables
one to garner accolades from university colleagues.
To support pacifism, multiculturalism, feminism, socialism, etc. hardly
severs connections with the liberal establishment.
Finally, though Hauerwas condemns James and Niebuhr for their pragmatism,
his own approach to the Christian faith is ultimately pragmatic.
Faith, to Hauerwas, works! It
works in different ways for him than for James and Niebuhr.
Whereas to James faith is personal, and what works brings personal
satisfaction, to Hauerwas faith is corporate.
The community, above all, is what matters.
What the worshiping community discerns as true and good, what enables the
community to function well, is what counts.
For Hauerwas, the church community validates itself in non-violence, in
social justice, in Anabaptist separation from political powers.
But, ultimately, "witness" means validating one’s faith, not
testifying to the Risen Lord Jesus!
*********************
Unlike Hauerwas, the 1999-2000 Gifford lecturer, Ralph McInerny, a
professor of philosophy at Notre Dame University (as well as the author of the
"Father Dowling" mystery stories which were serialized in a television
series several years ago), cheerfully embraced the calling to do "natural
theology" in Characters in Search of Their Author (Notre Dame:
University of Notre Dame Press, c. 2001).
He writes clearly, directly, determined to uphold the philosophy of St.
Thomas Aquinas. Whereas Hauerwas
employs irony, polemic, sometimes tortuous expositions, McInerny writes with a
certain structured serenity. In
part, as he says, "There are two kinds of philosopher:
one kind denies the obvious, the other kind states the obvious.
I am of the latter kind" (p. 119).
The book’s title is explained thusly:
"It has been said that life is a book in which we set out to write one
story and end by writing another. Deflective
surprises are due to chance or, as men have thought from time immemorial, to
another author in whose drama we are but players.
A play within a play. How can
we not be in search of our author?" (p. 3).
There is an Ultimate Playwright, McInerny believes, and "We are to God
as characters to their author" (p. 4). To
grasp the plot, the follow the action, much can be learned through a careful
study of the natural world he has made.
Trusting one’s reason, upholding the dignity of traditional philosophy,
puts one in a counter-cultural position today.
Since Rene Descartes shifted philosophers’ attention from the external
to the internal world in the 17th century, increasing numbers of thinkers have
assumed that "There is no reality sans phrase, only interpreted
reality, what we make of it" (p. 43). Descartes’
stance undergirds a "fashionable nihilism among influential philosophers,"
markedly akin to the "radical chic" Thomas Wolfe detailed in the plush
Noting the same pragmatic tendencies Hauerwas condemns, McInerny says
that for great numbers of thinkers today "Language is no longer the sign of
thought and thought is no longer the grasp of nature, of essence, of the way
things are. We are thrown back on
language itself, and to language is assigned the great task of constructing the
self we are and the world in which we live.
Language is a set of rules we adopt for purely pragmatic or utilitarian
reasons. We no longer seek to
achieve the true and avoid the false. Forget
about both of those. The only
question is, does it work, is it successful" (p. 26).
Ultimately, this relativistic, nihilistic view, clearly evident in
Nietzsche, cannot endure, for it conflicts with reality.
But it is difficult to rationally refute because its proponents deny the
legitimacy of reason!
Ironically, he says, facing the nihilistic irrationalism of
post-modernism, Catholic philosophers like himself are called to uphold the
integrity of the mind and the natural ability of man to know truth, even truth
about God. As John Paul II said, in
his great encyclical, Fides et ratio: ""One may define the human being,
therefore, as the one who seeks the truth’" (p. 121).
Ultimately, this means, as the Second Vatican Council affirmed, that
"Human dignity rests above all on the fact that man is called to communion
with God. This invitation to
converse with God is issued to a man as soon as he is born, for he only exists
because God has created him with love and through love continues to keep him in
existence. He cannot live fully in
the truth unless he freely acknowledges that love and entrusts himself to his
creator" (p. 30, citing Gaudium et Spes, n. 19).
This is, of course, no new task! In
the ancient world, Sophists propounded versions of nihilism, relativism,
subjectivism. Protagoras, the
Sophist who declared that "man is the measure of all things," was the
"first of the Pragmatists as well" (p. 45).
In his dialogue entitled Cratylus, Plato recorded that Protagoras
taught "that as things appear to me, then, so they actually are for me, and as
they appear to you, so they actually are for you" (p. 45).
Strongly reacting to such teachers, Socrates, Plato and Aristotle
carefully carved out the lineaments for classical philosophy, a perennial
philosophy ever ancient, ever new.
Centuries later, St. Augustine faced the same challenge -- skeptical, nihilistic philosophers -- and "wrote the Contra academicos to confront thinkers who held that nothing could be known. It is significant that Augustine as a believer saw the importance of addressing this attack on reason" (p. 45). Thinking rightly, he knew, means bringing one’s mind into alignment with the world that is. Right thinking, logic, reflects the logos, the Word enstructuring the world.
Aristotle, for example, insisted there are inescapable, undeniable "first principles." So, he said, enunciating the basic laws of thought:
Centuries later, "Thomas Aquinas,
like Aristotle, uses these three self-evident principles as if they were
synonymous. When he is speaking of
the first principles of practical reasoning, the precepts of Natural Law, he
draws an analogy between them and the first principles of reasoning as such.
He gives as the most fundamental judgment reason makes, non est simul
affirmare et negare" (p. 48, citing Summa Theologiae, 1-2.94.2).
One cannot affirm and deny that a given thing such as a tree or a
wildfire exists.
As Aquinas studied various pagan philosophers, he appreciated their
understanding of such principles. By
nature, without supernatural assistance, they reasoned rightly.
Still more: many of them
discerned truths identical with biblical truths.
For example, "Aristotle called the philosophical discipline that
culminates the lengthy task of philosophy theologia.
It has come to be called metaphysics, and is in effect the
wisdom the seeking of which gives philosophy its name" (p. 77).
Thus, to Aquinas, doing "natural theology" was obviously possible.
So he "coined a phrase to cover these naturally knowable truths about
God that had nonetheless been revealed. He
called them praeambula fidei. They
were distinguished from the other sort of truth about God, the kind that
dominates Scripture, which he dubbed mysteria fidei (p. 66).
Mysteries are not, however, irrational.
Were we wiser, we would understand the reasonableness--the logos--of our
faith. Indeed, Aquinas thought, "If
some of the things that have been revealed can be known to be true--the
preambles--then it is reasonable to accept that the others--they mysteries--are,
as they claim to be, true" (p. 67).
Turning to one of the most basic questions in natural theology, McInerny
argues that God’s existence is rationally demonstrable.
Rooted in Thomas Aquinas and the common sense tradition, he notes that
one thinks well, "not by sweeping away or casting a skeptical eye on the
thinking of ordinary folk, but by seeking there the well-springs of human
thinking as such. The amazing
assumption is that everybody already knows all sorts of things" (p. 118).
Moving from things any normal person knows, one discovers both the
necessary ontological truth that there must be a First Cause of all that is, as
well as certain moral "principia per se nota, precepts of natural
law" (p. 119).
So faith and reason conjoin. "Thomas
Aquinas discusses the act of religious faith in terms of Augustine’s
definition of it as "cum assensione cogitare:
thinking with assent" (p. 124).
Assisted by God’s grace, however limited by our human weakness, we can
think. And the more we think rightly
the better we grasp certain truths concerning God, man, and salvation.
Richard John Neuhaus’s appraisal of this book in First Things
merits repeating: "Ralph McInerny
never ceases to amaze. This book is
another such occasion. Here
erudition is joined by wit and lucidity in examining fundamental questions of
human existence in a manner that is both accessible to the general reader and an
intellectual challenge to the specialist. Prof.
McInerny provides a reliable, and enjoyable, guide to reasoned faith and
faithful reason."
###